Searle's Chinese Box: The Chinese Room Argument and Artificial Intelligence by Larry Hauser 
TITLE PAGE | PREFACE | ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS | ABSTRACT| TABLE_OF_CONTENTS | GLOSSARY | INTRODUCTION | CHAPTER_1
| CHAPTER_2 | CHAPTER_3 | CHAPTER_4 | CHAPTER_5 | CHAPTER_6 | BIBLIOGRAPHY 
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Abbott, Barbara. 1989. Nondescriptionality and Natural Kind Terms. Linguistics and Philosophy 12:269-291.

Abbott, Barbara, and Larry Hauser. 1992. Natural language and thought. In Proceedings of the Conference on Cognition and Representation, ed. J. T. Kearns, W. J. Rapaport, E. Segal, L. Talmy. SUNY Buffalo Center for Cognitive Science Technical Report 92-12. Presented at the SUNY Buffalo Center for Cognitive Science Conference on Cognition and Representation, April 4, 1992.

Alcock, J. E. 1987. Parapsychology: Science of the anomalous or search for the soul? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10:553-643.

Alexander, Samuel. 1927. Space, time, and deity. 2. London: MacMillan.

Anderson, David. 1987. Is the Chinese room the real thing? Philosophy 62:389-393.

Anscombe, G. E. M. 1963. Intention. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Aristotle. Nichomachean ethics. In Basic works of Aristotle. Ed. Richard McKeon. Trans. W. D. Ross, 935-1126. New York: Random House.

Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A materialist theory of mind. London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.

Augusta, Ada, Countess of Lovelace. 1842. Translator's notes to L. F. Menabrea's `Sketch of the analytical engine invented by Charles Babbage, Esq.'. In Faster than thought: A symposium on digital computing machines, ed. B. V. Bowden, 362-408. New York: Pitman Publishing Co.

Austin, John L. 1946. Other minds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement XX:148-187. ------. 1957. A plea for excuses. In Classics of analytic philosophy, ed. R. Ammerman, 379-398. Indianapolis: Hackett Inc.

Baker, Lynne Rudder. 1987. Saving belief: a critique of physicalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Baldwin, J. M. (ed). 1960. Dictionary of philosophy and psychology. Vol. I.  Ed. ------. Gloucester, MA: Peter Smith.

Bayle, Pierre. 1697. Rorarius. Trans. Richard H. Popkin. In Historical and critical dictionary, 213-254. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

Bem, D. J. 1967. Self-perception: An alternative interpretation of cognitive dissonance phenomena. Psychological Review 74:183-200. ------. 1972. Self-perception theory. In Advances in experimental social psychology, ed. L. Berkowitz. New York: Academic Press.

Block, Ned. 1978. Troubles with functionalism. In Perception and cognition: Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 9, ed. W. Savage. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

------. 1990. The computer model of the mind. In An invitation to cognitive science, vol. 3, ed. D Obershon and E. E. Smith, 247-289. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

------. 1990. Consciousness and accessibility. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13(4):596-598.

Boden, Margaret A. 1988. Escaping from the Chinese room. In The philosophy of artificial intelligence, ed. Margaret Boden, 89-104. New York: Oxford University Press. Originally appeared as Chapter 8 of Boden, Computer models of the mind. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge (1988).

------. 1990. The philosophy of artificial intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press.

Boghossian, Paul. 1989. Rule following considerations. Mind 98:507-549.

Boolos, George S., and Richard C. Jeffrey. 1974. Computability and logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bowden, B. V. 1953. Faster than thought: a symposium on digital computing. Ed. B. V. Boden. New York: Pitman Publishing Co.

Brentano, Franz. 1874. Psychology from the empirical standpoint. Ed. Linda L. McAlister. Trans. Antos C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell and Linda L. McAlister. New York: Humanities Press. 1973 translation with revisions of 1924 ed. of Psychologie vom empirishen standpunkt.

Broad, Charlie Dunbar. 1925. The mind and its place in nature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Bundy, Alan, and Stellan Ohlsson. 1987. The nature of AI principles. In The foundations of artificial intelligence, ed. Derek Partridge and Yorick Wilks, 135-154. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Cam, Phillip. 1990. Searle on strong AI. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68(1, March):103-108.

Campbell, C. A. 1957. Has the Self "Free Will"? In On selfhood and Godhood, 158-179. London: Allen & Urwin.

Carleton, Lawrence. 1984. Programs, language understanding, and Searle. Synthese 59:219-230.

Chandrasekaran, B. 1990. What kind of information processing is intelligence. In The foundations of artificial intelligence, ed. Derek Partridge and Yorick Wilks, 14-46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Chao, Y. R. 1959. Ambiguity in Chinese. In Studia seria Bernhard Karlgren dedicata. Copenhagen.

Chomsky, Noam. 1965. Methodological preliminaries. In Aspects of the theory of syntax, 3-63. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

------. 1966. Linguistics and Descartes. In Historical foundations of cognitive science, 71-79. Dordrecht, Holland: Kluwer. Reprinted from Cartesian linguistics: A chapter in the history of rational thought (Harper & Rowe, Publishers, Inc.), pp. 3-13.

------. 1990. Accessibility "in principle." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13(4):600-601.

Church, Alonzo. 1936. An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory. American Journal of Mathematics 58:345-363.

Churchland, Paul, and Patricia Smith Churchland. 1990. Could a machine think? Scientific American 262(1, January):32-39.

Churchland, Paul. 1988. Matter and consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

Cole, David. 1984. Thought and thought experiments. Philosophical Studies 45:431-444.

------. 1991b. Artificial minds: Cam on Searle. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69(3):329-333.

------. 1991b. Artificial Intelligence and Personal Identity. Synthese 88:399-417.

Cummins, Robert. 1989. Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford Books.

Davidson, Donald. 1964. Actions, reasons, and causes. In Essays on actions and events, 3-20. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

------. 1967. Causal Relations. In Essays on actions and events, 149-162. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

------. 1969. Individuation of Events. In Essays on actions and events, 163-180. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

------. 1970. Mental Events. In Essays on actions and events, 207-227. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

------. 1974. Psychology as philosophy. In Essays on actions and events, 229-244. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Davis, Martin. 1965. The undecidable: Basic papers on undecidable propositions, unsolvable problems and computable functions. New York: Raven Press.

Dennett, Daniel. 1980. The milk of human intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:429-430.

------. 1981. True believers. In The intentional stance, 15-32. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Bradford Books.

------. 1987a. Evolution, error, and intentionality. In The intentional stance, 288-321. Cambridge: MIT Press. ------. 1987b. Fast thinking. In The intentional stance, 323-337. Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Books.

------. 1987c. The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Derrida, Jacques. 1977a. Signature Event Context. Trans. Samuel Weber and Jeffrey Mehlman. In Limited Inc, 1-24. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. ------. 1977b. Limited Inc. a b c.... Trans. Samuel Weber. In Limited Inc, 29-110. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

Descartes, RenJ. 1628. Rules for the direction of the mind. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. I, 7-78. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1637. Discourse on method. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. I, 109-151. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1642. Meditations on first philosophy. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. II, 1-62. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1644. Principles of philosophy. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. I, 177-291. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1646. Letter to the Marquess of Newcastle, 23 November, 1646. Trans. Anthony Kenney. In Descartes' Philosophical letters, 205-208. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

------. 1647a. Preface to the French Edition. Principles of philosophy. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. I, 173-176. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1647b. Letter to Henry More. Trans. L. Cohen Rosenfield. Annals of Science 1(1, 1936).

------. 1649. Letter to More, 5 February 1649. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. III, 360-367. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Descartes, RenJ, Johannes Caterus, Marin Mersenne, Thomas Hobbes, Antoine Arnauld, Pierre Gassendi, and Pierre Bourdin. 1642. Objections and replies. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. II, 66-383. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Devitt, Michael. 1990. Meanings just ain't in the head. In Meaning and method: Essays in honor of Hilary Putnam, ed. George Boolos, 79-104. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Doyle, Jon. 1988. Big problems for artificial intelligence. AI Magazine 20:19-22.

Dretske, Fred. 1985. Machines and the mental. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 59(3, November):23-33.

Dreyfus, H., and S. Dreyfus. 1986. Mind over machine. New York: Free Press/Macmillan Inc.

Dreyfus, Hubert. 1979. What computers can't do. New York: Harper Colophon.

Fisher, John A. 1988. The wrong stuff: Chinese rooms and the nature of understanding. Philosophical Investigations 11(4):279-299.

Fodor, Jerry A., and Ernest Lepore. 1992. Holism: a shopper's guide. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell. Fodor, Jerry A. 1974. Special sciences, or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese 28:97-115.

------. 1975. The language of thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.

------. 1980. Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:63-109.

------. 1986a. Banish DisContent. In Mind and cognition, ed. W. G. Lycan, 420-438. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. First appeared in Language, Mind and Logic edited by J. Butterfield, Cambridge University Press, 1986.

------. 1986b. Individualism and supervenience. In Psychosemantics, 27-54. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987. Originally appeared in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society for 1986.

------. 1987. Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

------. 1989. Making mind matter more. In A theory of content and other essays, 137-159. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990. Originally appeared in Philosophical Topics 17: 59-79.

-------. 1990. A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Frege, Gottlob. 1892. On sense and reference. Trans. Max Black. In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. Peter Geach and Max Black. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

G`del, Kurt. 1934. On undecidable propositions of formal mathematical systems. In The undecidable, ed. Martin Davis, 39-74. Hewlett, NY: Raven Press.

Goel, Vinod. 1991. Notationality and the information processing mind. Minds and Machines 1(2):129-166.

Goodman, Nelson, and W. V. Quine. 1947. Steps toward a constructive nominalism. In Problems and projects, Nelson Goodman, 173-198. Originally published in Journal of Symbolic Logic 12: 105-122.

Gregory, Richard. 1987. In defense of artificial intelligence -- a reply to John Searle. In Mindwaves, ed. Colin Blakemore and Susan Greenfield, 235-244. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Grice, H. P. 1957. Meaning. Philosophical Review LXVI:377-388.

Gunderson, Keith. 1971. Mentality and machines. New York: Anchor Books.

------. 1990. Consciousness and intentionality: robots with and without the right stuff. In Propositional attitudes: the role of content in logic, language, and mind, ed. A. C. Anderson and J. Owens, 285-324. Stanford, CA: CLSI Publications.

Hanna, Joseph. 1968. An explication of `explication'. Philosophy of Science 31(1, March):28-44. Hanna, Patricia. 1985. Causal powers and cognition. Mind 94:53-63.

Harman, Gilbert. 1990. Intentionality: Some distinctions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:607-608.

Harnad, Stevan. 1982. Consciousness: An afterthought. Cognition and Brain Theory 5:29-47.

------. 1989a. Minds, machines and Searle. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 1(1):5-25. ------. 1989b. Editorial commentary on Libet. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12:183.

------. 1990. The symbol grounding problem. Physica D 42:335-346. North Holland.

------. 1991. Other bodies, other minds: a machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem. Minds and Machines 1:5-25.

Hauser, Larry. 1992. Act, aim, and unscientific explanation. Philosophical Investigations 15(10, October 1992):313-323.

------. 1993a. Why isn't my pocket calculator a thinking thing? Minds and Machines 3(1, February 1993):3-10.

------. 1993b. The sense of "thinking." Minds and Machines 3(1, February 1993):12-21.

------. 1993c. Thought, Computation, and Intrinsicality. Kalamazoo, MI: Michigan Academy of Arts and Sciences, Philosophy Section, March 5.

Hayes, P. J. 1982. Introduction. In Proceedings of the Cognitive Curricula Conference, vol. 2, ed. P. J. Hayes and M. M. Lucas. Rochester, NY: University of Rochester.

Hayes, Patrick, Stevan Harnad, Donald Perlis, and Ned. Block. 1992. Virtual symposium on virtual mind. Minds and Machines 2(3):217-238.

Hempel, Carl. 1949. The logical analysis of psychology. In Readings in philosophical analysis, ed. H. Feigel and W. Sellars. New York: Appleton Century Crofts.

Hodges, Andrew. 1983. Alan Turing: The enigma. New York: Simon & Schuster/Touchstone.

Humberstone, I. L. 1972. A note on `instead of'. In York papers in linguistics, vol. 2, 137-142.

Husserl Edmund. 1913. Logical investigations. Trans. J. N. Findley. New York: Humanities Press. 1970 translation of the second edition of Logische untersuchungen.

Jackson, Frank. 1982. Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly 32:127-136.

Jacquette, Dale. 1989. Adventures in the Chinese room. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XLIX(4, June):606-623.

James, William. 1950. Principles of psychology. New York: Dover Publications.

Johnson-Laird, Philip N. 1988. The computer and the mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Kim, Jaegwon. 1973. Causation, nomic subsumption, and the concept of event. Journal of Philosophy 70:217-236.

------. 1973. Causation, nomic subsumption, and the concept of an event. Journal of Philosophy LXX(8, April 26):217-226.

------. 1976. Events as property exemplifications. In Action theory, ed. Myles Brand and Douglas Walton. Dordrecht: Reidel.

------. 1984a. Self-understanding and rationalizing explanations. Philosophia Naturalis 21(1984):309-320.

------. 1984b. Psychophysical laws. In Actions and events: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson, ed. Ernest Lepore and Brian McLaughlin, 369-386. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1988. Explanatory realism, causal realism, and explanatory exclusion. In Midwest studies in philosophy, 225-240.

------. 1989. Mechanism, purpose, and explanatory exclusion. In Philosophical perspectives, 3: Philosophy of mind and action theory, 77-108. 1989.

------. 1992a. Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LII(1, March 1992):1-26.

------. 1992b. The nonreductivist's troubles with mental causation. In Mental causation, ed. John Heil and Alfred Mele. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kleene, Stephen C. 1936. General recursive functions of natural numbers. Math Annual 112:727-742.

Kripke, Saul A. 1971. Naming and necessity. In Semantics of natural language, ed. D. Davidson and G. Harmon, 253-355. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Reidel.

------. 1982. Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kronfeld, Amichai. 1990. Reference and computation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. 2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Lakoff, George P. 1970b. A note on vagueness and ambiguity. Linguistic Inquiry I(3):357-359.

LatanJ, B., and J. M. Darley. 1970. The unresponsive bystander: Why doesn't he help? New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

Leiber, Justin. 1985. Can animals and machines be persons?: A dialogue. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co. ------.

1991. Invitation to cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

Lewis, David. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. New York: Basil Blackwell.

Lycan, William. 1992. A new argument for the representational theory of mind. Paper presented at the Department of Philosophy's Conference on Belief and Belief Attribution, University of Rochester. Rochester, NY, May 1991. Forthcoming in Mind and Language.

Lyons, William. 1985. On Searle's "solution" to the mind-body problem. Philosophical Studies 48:291-294. ------. 1986. The Disappearance of Introspection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

MacQueen, Kenneth G. 1990. Not a trivial consequence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:193-194.

Maeir, N. R. F. 1931. Reasoning in humans: II. The solution of a problem and its appearance in consciousness. Journal of Comparative Psychology 12:181-194.

Malcolm, Norman. 1958. Knowledge of other minds. Journal of Philosophy LV. Reprinted in The Philosophy of mind, ed. V. C. Chappell (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1962).

------. 1968. The conceivability of mechanism. Philosophical Review 77:45-72. Reprinted in Gary Watson (ed.), Free will (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982).

Maloney, Christopher. 1987. The right stuff. Synthese 70:349-372.

Marr, David. 1977. Artificial intelligence: a personal view. In The foundations of artificial intelligence: a sourcebook, ed. Derek Partridge and Yorick Wilks, 97-107. New York: Cambridge University Press. First published in Artificial Intelligence, Vol. 9 (1977), pp. 37-48.

McCarthy, John. 1980. Beliefs, machines, and theories. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:435.

McKeon, Richard (ed.). 1941. Basic works of Aristotle. Ed. ------. New York: Random House.

Millikan, Ruth. 1984. Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Morgan, J. L. 1972. Syntactic form and conversational import -- some interactions. In Papers from the University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Linguistics Group First Annual Symposium on Limiting the Domain of Linguistics, ed. D. Cohen, 37-53. Milwaukee: University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Linguistics Group.

Nagel, Thomas. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83:435-450.

------. 1986. The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

------. 1987. Free will. In What does it all mean?, 47-58. New York: Oxford University Press. Nelkin, Norton. What is consciousness? Forthcoming in Philosophy of Science.

Newell, Allen, and Simon H. A. 1963. GPS, a program that simulates human thought. In Computers and thought, ed. Edward A. Feigenbaum and Julian Feldman, 279-293. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1963.

Newell, Allen. 1979. Physical symbol systems. Lecture at the La Jolla Conference on Cognitive Science.

Nisbett, R. E., and N. Bellows. 1976. Accuracy and inaccuracy in verbal reports about influences on evaluations. Unpublished manuscript. University of Michigan. Cited in Nisbett & Wilson 1977.

Nisbett, R. E., and S. Valins. 1972. Perceiving the causes of ones own behavior. New York: General Learning Press.

Nisbett, Richard E., and Timothy DeCamp Wilson. 1977. Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84(3, may):231-259.

Oppenheim, Paul, and Hilary Putnam. 1958. Unity of science as a working hypothesis. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, ed. Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven and Grover Maxwell. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Partridge, Derek, and Yorick Wilks. 1990a. Does AI have a methodology that is different from software engineering? In The foundations of artificial intelligence, ed. ------, 363-372. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1990b. The foundations of artificial intelligence. Ed. ------. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Penrose, Roger. 1989. The emperor's new mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Pucetti, Roland. 1980. The chess room: further demythologizing of strong AI. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:441-442.

Putnam, Hilary. 1960. Minds and machines. In Mind, language and reality: Collected papers, vol. 2, 362-384. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1967. The nature of mental states. In Mind, language and reality: Collected papers, vol. 2, 429-440. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1975. The meaning of `meaning'. In Language, mind, and knowledge: Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 7, ed. Keith Gunderson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

------. 1988. Representation and reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pylyshyn, Zenon. 1984. Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Quine, Willard O. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

------. 1975. Mind and verbal dispositions. In Mind and language, ed. Samuel Guttenplan, 83-95. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Rapaport, William J. 1986. Searle's experiments with thought. Philosophy of Science 53:271-279.

------. 1988. Syntactic semantics: foundations of computational natural language understanding. In Aspects of artificial intelligence, ed. James H. Fetzer, 81-131. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer.

------. 1993. Because mere calculating isn't thinking: Reply to Hauser. Minds and Machines 3(1, February 1993). Rey, Georges. 1986. Searle's `Chinese room'. Philosophical Studies 50:169-185.

Russell, Bertrand. 1912. Principles of philosophy. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

------. 1948. Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson & Company.

Savitt, Steven F. 1982. Searle's demon and the brain simulator. Behavioral and brain sciences 5(2):342-343.

Schank, Roger C., and Robert P. Abelson. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Press.

Schank, Roger C. 1977. Natural language, philosophy, and artificial intelligence. In Philosophical perspectives in artificial intelligence, 196-224. Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press.

Schiffer, Stephen R. 1987. Remnants of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Searle, John R., and Daniel Dennett. 1982. The myth of the computer. New York Review of Books 57(24/July):56-57.

------. 1990. "The emperor's new mind": An exchange. New York Review of Books XXXVII(10, June):58-60.

Searle, John R. 1971a. Speech acts. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1971b. What is a speech act? In The philosophy of language, ed. John Searle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

------. 1975a. Speech acts and recent linguistics. In Expression and meaning, 162-179. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1975b. Indirect speech acts. In Expression and meaning, 30-57. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1975c. A taxonomy of illocutionary acts. In Expression and meaning, 1-29. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1977. Reiterating the differences: A reply to Derrida. Glyph 2:198-208. John Hopkins.

------. 1978. Literal meaning. In Expression and meaning, 117-136. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1979a. What is an intentional state? Mind LXXXVIII:74-92.

------. 1979b. Intentionality and the use of language. In Meaning and use, ed. A. Margalit, 181-197. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel Publishing Co.

------. 1979c. The intentionality of intention and action. Inquiry 22:253-280.

------. 1979d. Metaphor. In Expression and meaning, 76-116. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1979e. Referential and attributive. In Expression and meaning, 137-161. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1979f. Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1980a. Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:417-424.

------. 1980b. Intrinsic intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:450-456.

------. 1980c. Analytic philosophy and mental phenomena. In Midwest studies in philosophy, vol. 5, 405-423. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

------. 1980d. The background of meaning. In Speech act theory and pragmatics, ed. J. R. Searle, F. Kiefer and M. Bierwisch, 221-232. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel Publishing Co.

------. 1982. The Chinese room revisited. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5(2):345-348.

------. 1983. Intentionality: an essay in the philosophy of mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1984a. Minds, brains, and science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

------. 1984b. Intentionality and its place in nature. Synthese 61:3-16.

------. 1985. Patterns, symbols and understanding. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8(4):742-743.

------. 1986. Meaning, communication and representation. In Philosophical grounds of rationality, ed. R. Grandy and xx, 209-226.

------. 1987. Indeterminacy, empiricism, and the first person. Journal of Philosophy LXXXIV(3, March):123-146.

------. 1988. Minds and brains without programs. In Mindwaves, ed. Colin Blakemore and Susan Greenfield, 209-233. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1989a. Reply to Jacquette. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XLIX(4):701-708.

------. 1989b. Consciousness, unconsciousness, and intentionality. Philosophical Topics XVII(1, spring):193-209. ------. 1989c. How performatives work. Linguistics and Philosophy 12:535-558.

------. 1990a. Is the brain's mind a computer program? Scientific American 262(1):26-31.

------. 1990b. Consciousness, unconsciousness and intentionality. In Propositional attitudes: the role of content in logic, language, and mind, ed. Anderson A. and J. Owens, 269-284. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information.

------. 1990c. Is the brain a digital computer? Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association 64(3):21-38.

------. 1990d. Forward to Amichai Kronfeld's Reference and computation. In Reference and computation, by Amichai Kronfeld, xii-xviii. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

------. 1990e. The causal powers of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:164.

------. 1990f. Consciousness, explanatory inversion, and cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:585-596.

------. 1990g. Who is computing with the brain? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:632-640.

------. 1991a. Meaning, intentionality and speech acts. In John Searle and his critics, ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick, 81-102. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1991b. The mind-body problem. In John Searle and his critics, ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick, 141-147. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1991c. Perception and the satisfactions of intentionality. In John Searle and his critics, ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick, 181-192. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1991d. Reference and intentionality. In John Searle and his critics, ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick, 227-241. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1991e. The background of intentionality and action. In John Searle and his critics, ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick, 289-299. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1991f. Explanation in the social sciences. In John Searle and his critics, ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick, 335-342. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

------. 1992. The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Searle, J. R., J. McCarthy, H. Dreyfus, M. Minsky, and S. Papert. 1984. Has artificial intelligence research illuminated human thinking? Annals of the New York City Academy of Arts and Sciences 426:138-160.

Searle, J. R., K. O. Apel, W. P. Alston, et al. 1991. John Searle and his critics. Ed. Ernest Lepore and Robert Van Gulick. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

Sharvy, Richard. 1985. It ain't the meat it's the motion. Inquiry 26:125-134.

Shopen, T. 1973. Ellipsis as grammatical indeterminacy. Foundations of Language 10(1):65-77.

Slovic, P., and S. Lichtenstein. 1971. Comparison of Bayesian and regression approaches to the study of information processing in judgment. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 6:649-744.

Smart J. J. C. 1958. Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review 68:141-156.

Stich, Stevan. 1983. From folk psychology to cognitive science: the case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Stillings, Neil A., Mark H. Feinstein, Jay L. Garfield, et al. 1987. Cognitive science: An introduction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Stipp, David. 1991. Does that computer have something on its mind? Wall Street Journal, Tuesday, March 19, A20.

Storms, M. D., and R. E. Nisbett. 1970. Insomnia and the attribution process. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 2:319-328.

Tanenbaum, Andrew S. 1976. Structured computer organization. Englewood Cliff, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Trakhtenbrot, Boris. 1963. Algorithms and automatic computing machines. Trans. J. Kristian, J. D. McCawley and S. A. Schmitt. Boston: D. C. Heath and Co.

Turing, Alan M. 1936-7. On computable numbers with an application to the Entsheidungsproblem. In The undecidable, ed. Martin Davis, 116-154. New York: Raven Press, 1965. Originally published in Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, ser. 2, vol. 42 (1936-7), pp. 230-265; corrections Ibid, vol. 43 (1937), pp. 544-546.

------. 1950. Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind LIX:433-460.

------. 1969. Intelligent machinery. Machine Intelligence 5(1969):3-23, ed. B. Meltzer and D. Michie.

Watson, John B. 1913. Psychology as the behaviorist views it. In Basic writings in the history of psychology, ed. R. I. Watson Sr., 272-281. New York: Oxford University Press, 1979. Originally published in Psychological Review, vol. 20, pp. 158-177.

------. 1924. Behaviorism. New York: Norton and Company, 1970.

Weick, K. E. 1966. Task acceptance dilemmas: A site for research on cognition. In Cognitive consistency, ed. S. Feldman. New York: Academic Press.

Weinberg, Gerald M. 1967. Computing machines. In Encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Paul Edwards, 168-173. New York: MacMillan.

Weinreich, U. 1966. Explorations in semantic theory. In Current trends in linguistics, vol. 3, ed. T. A. Sebeok, 395-477.

Weiskrantz, L. 1986. Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford: Clarendon.

Weiss, Thomas. 1990. Closing the Chinese room. Ratio (New Series) III(2):165-181.

Weizenbaum, Joseph. 1965. Eliza -- a computer program for the study of natural language communication between man and machine. Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery 9:36-45.

------. 1976. Computer power and human reason. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

Weydt, H. 1973. On G. Lakoff, `Instrumental adverbs and the concept of deep structure'. Foundations of Language 10(4):569-578.

Wilks, Yorick. 1982. Searle's straw man. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5(2):344-345.

Winograd, Terry. 1973. A procedural model of language understanding. In Computer models of thought and language, ed. R. Schank and K. Colby. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical investigations. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Zwicky, Arnold M., and Jerrold M. Sadock. 1975. Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In Syntax and semantics, ed. John Kimball, 1-36. New York: Academic Press.


TITLE PAGE | PREFACE | ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS | ABSTRACT| TABLE_OF_CONTENTS | GLOSSARY | INTRODUCTION | CHAPTER_1 | CHAPTER_2 | CHAPTER_3 | CHAPTER_4 | CHAPTER_5 | CHAPTER_6 | BIBLIOGRAPHY